Wednesday, October 24, 2007

Pyrrhonian Skepticism and Objective Values

In her article “Doing without objective values,” (Malcolm Schofield and Gisela Striker, eds., The Norms of Nature: Studies in Hellenistic Ethics, pp. 3-29.) Julia Annas states that in Sextus Empiricus’ arguments from the tenth Mode of Anesidemus, he is confusing moral realism with moral absolutism. Sextus proposes several arguments like the following: what is good by nature should be good for all, just as fire which is warm by nature warms all (PH III 179). But since different cultures have different beliefs about what is good, and are thus not similarly affected by what is good, we may conclude that nothing is good by nature. Hence, we should give up our beliefs about this or that object being good by nature and, suspending judgment, arrive at tranquility.

But, says Annas, this is a mistake since moral realism, which Sextus is trying to argue against, is not the same position as moral absolutism, which he actually argues against. Annas states that this confusion is one that “Sextus could reasonably have been expected to avoid,” (Annas 10) for three reasons. First, Sextus seems to argue that beliefs about what is good by nature are a source of anxiety, but that if we consider that goods are relative to persons or societies then we can suspend judgment on whether something is good by nature and achieve ataraxia. However, this supposition is unwarranted, since it could still be the case that a good relative to me is a real good, and this could presumably still be a cause of anxiety. Second, Annas produces Polystratus the Epicurean as an example of a philosopher who lived before Sextus and who made the distinction between moral realism and moral absolutism. And third, she points out that moral relativism is a far cry from skepticism, since the moral relativist will still have beliefs about what is good, even if it is relatively good.

I will grant here that Annas is correct in asserting that Sextus conflates the two positions, but I will offer responses to her arguments that this is a mistake that Sextus could and should have avoided. First, given Sextus’ overall project of producing ataraxia by whatever means necessary, it is unclear what advantage he would have gained in relation to his dogmatic opponents by distinguishing between moral realism and moral absolutism, given that most of his opponents would have held to both. Annas seems to be of the opinion that Sextus overlooked the possibility of his interlocutors’ taking refuge in the position that “this is really good, but only in relation to me” (Annas, 10). But while this is perhaps a possible move, it is, I think, highly improbable that Sextus’ opponents would have actually made such a move given their philosophical commitments, and thus Sextus is not to be blamed for not attempting to counter it.

And while Annas can point to one philosopher who made the distinction between moral realism and moral absolutism, this seems an insufficient objection unless it can be shown that this position was so widely held or influential as to warrant its own branch of skeptical arguments. No doubt Sextus, if confronted by a special individual case, could produce arguments suitable to his opponent’s particular dogmas; but in a work like PH, where he spends so little time on ethical issues, I believe it is sufficient for him to address the beliefs of the majority of his audience.

As to Annas’ third objection, it seems that she assumes that Sextus was arguing for a position (relativism) in order to get his opponents to accept the conclusion of his argument. If I am in fact reading her correctly, by way of reply I need only observe that Sextus did not advance relativistic arguments in order to get his opponents to be relativists, but in order to counterbalance their other ethical beliefs in an attempt to produce epoche and ataraxia. He is not committed to the position of relativism any more than he is committed to the position that fire is actually warm by nature. Thus, in light of Sextus' overall project I think that this particular criticism of Annas' is misguided.

4 comments:

William Rowley said...

Is moral realism for Annas the negation of moral nihilism (that there are no moral facts)? Is moral absolutism the view that moral facts are fixed by some sort of necessity (nomic, logical, metaphysical)?

Dan Issler said...

1) Basically yes, 2) "Moral absolutism, the belief that there are general rules or principles that apply to everybody without exception in all circumstances..." (Annas 9).

Carolin said...

I am interested in your opinion of the MA Phil program at Talbot. Is there a particular reason you chose this program over for example UC Santa Barbara? Obviously it is a Christian school, but outside of that, why did you choose it.

William Rowley said...

My personal reasons for choosing Talbot won't generalize easily. After all, I was working at the school at the time and it was most fiscally and practically feasible for me to take classes while I was working there. Had that not been the case, I would have looked more seriously at other MA programs (especially funded ones), as Dan did.

But that said, apart from those pragmatic issues, there is a fair amount to recommend Talbot. The professors are quite good and model the conduct of philosophy very well. Despite the huge number of students in the program (Biola doesn't have an endowment, so they tend to have their departments over-filled with students for the tuition $$. Talbot's no exception, thoguh they apparently have capped enrollment) it is possible to get face time with the professors on a regular basis. Talbot's placement record for getting into PhD programs is pretty good, excellent even for the class of evangelical schools.

Different goals will find Talbot more helpful in achieving them than others. Talbot gets some students who are mainly interested in philosophy as a secondary interest - some are interested in going on to theology, biblical studies, or are already a pastor, interested in becoming a better thinker either for itself or to be better at being a pastor. Talbot is EXCELLENT for these people - I wouldn't recommend any program I know of higher for that goal. However, for the philosophy student who is interested in going onto do philosophy at a PhD level, there are more trade-offs, such as class size, relatively small faculty size, that getting an MA requires a LOT of Bible/Theology classes, and that Talbot does not require a thesis.

I think I was as well-prepared as most of the students admitted my year at Rochester and my impression from talking with other grads is that in terms of preparation for a PhD program, Talbot is quite good.

I'd be happy to answer any further questions you have if you write me at wrowley AT mail Dot rochester D OT edu.