Friday, June 20, 2008
Unconscious Inference
Thursday, June 5, 2008
Content Externalism
Monday, March 17, 2008
Stoic Views on Value
Cato states that what is valuable is that which is “either itself in accordance with nature, or brings about something that is” (III.20) and that the only things worth choosing are things that are valuable. He then describes “appropriate actions” as being impulses directed towards selecting what is in accordance with nature: initially as infants we seek to preserve our own existence, but as we become able to exercise our reason we see an overall order and pattern in the world that we come to seek for its own sake. Thus, we discover that acting virtuously, i.e. acting in accordance with the order and pattern of nature, is the only thing that is truly valuable and thus truly choiceworthy. Virtue is necessary and sufficient for eudaimonia, and all else is indifferent. But of the things that are indifferent, some such as health and beauty are in accordance with nature, and are thus to be preferred over their opposites such as sickness. It seems to me as though Cato is saying that virtue is the only thing we need in order to be happy, but if we are presented with the option of either having or not having certain external goods, we will take those things that are in accordance with nature. So, the Stoic sage will not go out of his way to obtain health and money, but if they happen to come his way he will not reject them. This view of virtue, taken with the Stoic belief that virtue is within our power, shows that for the Stoics happiness is something that is completely within our power, and not dependent on things such as external goods that are often beyond our control.
Cato sees the potential difficulty in making a distinction between what is to be chosen and what is to be selected, and at III.22-24 he tries to illustrate how the Stoics can maintain this distinction while still maintaining that virtue is the only thing that is ultimately valuable. His example of archery is rather confused (why else does the archer practice his craft, if not for the sake of hitting the mark?) but his examples of acting and dancing seem to work better, since they accord somewhat with his account of virtue in that the craft is practiced for its own sake, and not for the sake of some external object. But even dancing and acting are not perfect examples, Cato says, because their success can depend partially on what is outside of the dancer’s or actor’s control, such as the audience’s reaction.
However, it seems to me that the distinction between what is choiceworthy and what is selected cannot be consistently maintained. Earlier in III.20 Cato stated that what is in accordance with nature is valuable, and thus choiceworthy. But at III.44, Cato admits that health has some value, although he does not admit that it is a “good.” He seems to be saying that the value of heath and the value of virtue are different in kind, even if his comparisons of them at III.45 seem to imply a difference in degree. But he is faced with a dilemma: either health is in fact in accordance with nature, and thus is valuable and choiceworthy, or else it is not choiceworthy, and thus can be neither valuable nor in accordance with nature, and thus there would be no grounds for preferring it to sickness. As it is, Cato seems to want to say that health is both in accordance with nature, and yet not choiceworthy, which is inconsistent with his own stated system of value.
Friday, February 29, 2008
A Mereological Argument for Theism
Thursday, February 7, 2008
On the Nature of Numbers
I. It seems viciously circular: if 2 is the set of all pairs, what are pairs other than a set of two objects? The same objection seems to hold for defining 3 as the set of all triples, etc.
II. Even if this kind of definition can be used for the natural numbers, I am at a loss to understand how numbers such as fractions, irrational roots, pi, imaginary numbers, and negative numbers are to be defined in terms of sets of objects.
III. If “pairs” is understood to mean “pairs of physical objects,” then it would seem that in a possible world with only two physical objects, numbers larger than two could not exist, since e.g. “the set of all triples” would be empty.
IV. Or again, take two possible worlds which each contain only twenty physical objects, with the stipulation that each world contains objects that are entirely different than the objects in the other. In this case, it would seem that “2” in one world would not be identical to “2” in the other, since the set defined as “the set of all pairs” would have different members in each possible world.
Thales' Well
Aristotle on Knowledge and Necessity
The determinist’s argument in De Int. 9 (as given by Aristotle and interpreted by Richard Sorabji[1]) runs as follows: it is either true or false that event X will occur. If the statement “X will happen” turns out to be true, then it will have been true in the past. But if the statement “X will happen” was true in the past, then there is no point to deliberating whether or not to bring it about that X, since “X will happen” was true in the past, and the past cannot be altered. Thus, “X will happen” is necessarily true.
As Sorabji points out, Aristotle seems to accept the inference from the premise that any given statement is either true or false to the determinist conclusion. According to what Sorabji calls the traditional interpretation, Aristotle answers the determinist by arguing that predictive statements like “X will happen” are not yet true or false, but become true or false when X actually happens (or becomes inevitable). Sorabji finds this response unsatisfying, because e.g. if a statement’s being true means that it corresponds to a state of affairs in the world (which was a fairly common understanding of “true” for the Greeks) then the statement “there will be a sea battle tomorrow” is true (when uttered) if in fact it corresponds to a state of affairs, viz. the sea battle happening tomorrow; to speak of it as “not yet true” seems odd (Sorabji 101).
Sorabji’s own solution is to deny the inference between the premise that any given statement is either true or false to the determinist conclusion by making reference to one’s power, or lack of power, to bring about a state of affairs. Thus, if the statement “X will happen” turns out to be true, i.e. actually happens, then I do not have it in my power to make it the case that not-X, since X has already happened and I cannot alter the past. But, Sorabji thinks that this scenario is disanalogous to a situation in which I have been told “X will happen,” but X has not yet happened. Sorabji argues that since the event X still lies in the future, we still have the power to bring about not-X, and thus even if the statement “X will happen” does turn out to be true, it is not necessarily true, as the determinist thinks.
However, it seems to me as though something like Sorabji’s reply was addressed by Aristotle. At 19a7-23, Aristotle argues that it is false that all events happen of necessity: before an event X happens, both X and not-X are possible states of affairs. Since not-X is possible, then if X happens, it cannot have happened necessarily since it was in some agent’s power to bring about not-X. This passage seems to mirror Sorabji’s discussion of irrevocability in the first paragraph on p. 102, and Aristotle seems to argue here for the same disanalogy between past events and future events that Sorabji does.
Returning to Sorabji’s objection that it seems as though statements about the future should be said to be actually true or false depending on whether they in fact correspond to a state of affairs, it seems to me that Aristotle could answer that they are not yet true or false simply because they do not yet correspond to a state of affairs, and that only when they can truly be said to correspond, or fail to correspond, to a state of affairs can they be said to be true or false. It seems to me that this is the line Aristotle takes in his conclusion to this section at 19b1. Thus it appears that Aristotle argues both for a qualified principle of bivalence (cf. Sorabji p. 94-95) and against the determinist’s belief that all events happen of necessity.
[1] Sorabji, Richard. “Necessity, Cause, and Blame: Perspectives on Aristotle’s Theory.” Duckworth, 1980, pp. 91-103.
Friday, January 25, 2008
A Phenomenological Challenge for Evidentialism
A friend of mine turned me onto this paper by PVI. It's very interesting, and fits in with some reading I'm doing for a seminar on rational disagreement. It's a fascinating paper - I enjoyed reading it - but I almost always enjoy reading PVI, whether or not you agree with him on a given point, he's a delightful writer.
At any rate, I see a challenge for evidentialism here. I mean by 'evidentialism' something like the following: p is justified for S at t iff p fits S's evidence E at t (cribbed directly from Conee and Feldman's Evidentialism). In the context, what PVI is talking about beliefs that we are "hardwired" for, beliefs that we come to "automatically" without having to resort to discursive reasoning.
I think there is also something to what PVI is saying - phenomenologically, there are many beliefs we arrive at that we don't obviously carefully survey our evidence, weigh it, and believe. Belief is frequently automatic. My belief in other minds is one of these things - if I walk into the grad office and see two students sitting there, I don't make a reasoned argument that I am aware of to the conclusion that by certain analogies with my own mind and behavior, the two objects in the room are actually intelligent human beings with minds more or less like my own. I think that PVI might be right also about the material world. I don't wake up in the morning, open my eyes, look out the window and conclude that the simplest explanation is that the things that I am experiencing are non-mental objects independent of my mind. However, I believe it.
So, there's a phenomenological challenge to evidentialism. Evidentialists need a way to account for automatic beliefs that seem to be justified. But I think that the problem is hardly one for evidentialism simpliciter, as an account of justification, but rather with evidentialism as part of the analysis of knowledge. The way I'm inclined to go with this (at least at the moment) is to take the automatic part of belief formation to be part of a basing relation that either causally or otherwise pairs beliefs and evidence (cribbed again from Conee and Feldman).
Aside: for an access internalist, is it necessary that both the justifier of a belief and the basing relation be accessible to the knower?
[1] van Inwagen, Peter, "Is God an Unnecessary Hypothesis?" God and the Ethics of Belief ed. Andrew Dole and Andrew Chignell (Cambridge) 2005, p. 146